Answering the Critics of Precautionary Principle

From: Robina Suwol
Date: 14 May 2004
Time: 08:08:10
Remote Name: 68.116.132.26

Comments

RACHEL'S ENVIRONMENT & HEALTH NEWS #790
http://www.rachel.org
April 29, 2004

ANSWERING THE CRITICS OF PRECAUTION, Part 2

[Continued from Rachel's #789, available at http://www.rachel.org/bulletin/index.cfm?issue_ID=2431]

Here are more responses to some of the criticisms of precaution; naturally, these are not the only possible
responses.

Criticism #7: The precautionary principle is based on values and emotions and not on science.

Response #7: Everything we do is based on values. Of course the precautionary principle is based on values, but so is the old risk-based way of making decisions -- the two approaches just emphasize different values.

The precautionary principle makes one set of values explicit -- protecting humans and ecosystems -- and puts that out front. Under the "old way" we try to hide our values behind "science," using scientific uncertainty as a cover for valuing short-term, private gain and ignoring the long-term and
public/environmental consequences of our actions.

Even science starts with values. Scientific inquiry always begins by asking a question, and the questions that scientists choose to ask arise from particular values, particular assumptions about what is important.[1] So with science and precaution, as with all of life -- values come first.[2] There is nothing wrong with this. Indeed, there is no way to escape it. Making values explicit helps people understand what's really going on, and clarifies our choices as citizens.

Advocates of the precautionary principle definitely don't turn their backs on science, But they also don't turn their backs on other kinds of knowledge. Science is not the only valid way of knowing about the world; other kinds of knowledge can be useful to decision-makers -- historical knowledge, business knowledge, spiritual knowledge, local knowledge, community preferences, cultural values, artistic perceptions, and so on, can all play a valuable role in informing decision-makers.

Science cannot tell us what's best for society. Scientific experts can provide valuable information, but when it comes to setting political goals and making public policies, scientists have no special expertise. As the European Environment Agency has said, "Science should be on tap, not on top." We citizens should decide what we really want (our goals), take all available scientific information into account, take all the other relevant information into account, then do our best to become wise decision-makers.

Who are wise decision-makers?

** Those who are willing to monitor the consequences of their decision, to try to learn from past choices;[3]

** who are willing to revisit past decisions periodically, update their assessments, and modify policies accordingly;

** who favor decisions that can be reversed if things start to go sour;

** who experiment and try to learn before making a full-scale commitment down an unknown path;

** who consider all available alternatives, considering both costs and benefits before proceeding;

** who involve affected parties in decisions from the earliest stages when questions are being asked and goals set;

** who consider intergenerational equity in all decisions, asking whether we are saddling future generations with costs (or diminished opportunities) that we ourselves should be bearing;

** who ask whether justice and fairness are enhanced by the decision;

** who ask whether the decision will increase or decrease inequalities within and between communities;

** who ask what effect the decision will have on the most vulnerable and least capable among us.

Criticism #8: The precautionary principle envisions a new role for government, one without precedent or legitimacy.

Response #8: On the contrary, government has an ancient legal obligation to take precautionary action, to protect the public trust.

The Public Trust Doctrine is a legal doctrine handed down to us from Roman law, through English law, into the law of the 13 original colonies and now the states.[4]

The public trust doctrine asserts that the sovereign (in our case, state government) has an inalienable duty (a duty that cannot be denied or given away) to protect the common wealth -- air, water, wildlife, public health, our genetic heritage, and more -- which we all inherit and own together and none of us owns individually.[4]

As trustee, government must protect the trust assets (nature and human health) for the trust beneficiaries (present and future generations). Government even has a duty to protect the trust assets against harmful actions by the beneficiaries themselves, and so from time to time government must limit some of the prerogatives of private property in order to protect the common wealth for present and future generations.

In carrying out its duty to protect the public trust, government has a duty to anticipate harm, to look ahead to protect the trust against impending threats.[5] If government waits until harm can be demonstrated beyond doubt, then it will be too late -- the trust property will be damaged and government will have failed in its duty as trustee.

The precautionary principle provides a way for government to fulfill its responsibility to protect the public trust, to anticipate and avoid harm, to foresee and forestall.

Criticism #9: Risk assessments rely on conservative assumptions and so they embody all the "precaution" we need.

Response #9: Risk assessments typically examine only a single option, not a range of alternatives. Therefore, risk assessments don't ask the basic precautionary question, "How can we minimize harm while achieving our goal?"

Because basic data are often not available about environment and health risks, risk assessors substitute best professional judgments and estimates. Furthermore, risk assessments try to compensate for unknowns and unknowables by applying "uncertainty factors" of 10 or 100 or 1000. As a result, two equally qualified risk assessors working with the same basic data can reach vastly different conclusions about risk.[6] Peer review of risk assessments by all stakeholders can reduce the range of disagreement, but it remains true that the assessment of risks can vary greatly, depending upon who is doing the risk assessment. As the first administrator of U.S. Environmental Protection Agency, William Ruckelshaus, said in 1984: "We should remember that risk assessment data can be like the captured spy: If you torture it long enough, it will tell you anything you want to know."[7]

Therefore, a risk assessment of a single option is not precautionary. Indeed, risk assessments are often used merely to argue that a certain amount of harm is justifiable, not to learn how much harm is avoidable.

Furthermore, instead of accepting that the burden of producing needed information falls on the party who is seeking to impose risks on society, risk assessors often try to make up for the lack of basic data by applying "uncertainty factors," as if guesswork could adequately substitute for real knowledge. This
is not precautionary in any sense of the word.

Risk assessment might play a role in a precautionary decision process by assessing the risks -- and the benefits -- of all available alternatives. The work of risk assessors could then be considered, along with many other factors, in the decision.

Criticism #10: Precaution requires proof of safety, which is impossible.

Response #10: Precaution does not require proof of safety -- it requires that the creator of risks shall make a best effort to acquire the information needed to assess the possible harms from the activity -- an effort that is open and subject to peer review by all affected parties. It requires acceptance of the
community's stake in the outcome. It requires a commitment to ongoing monitoring and open reporting as the activity unfolds, and agreeing to pay for any harm that ensues, and taking responsibility for remediation as needed.

But there is still no guarantee that any particular firm will be able to make good on the financial commitment inherent in "agreeing to pay for any harm that ensues, and taking responsibility for remediation as needed." If the Superfund program teaches us anything, it teaches us that even large
firms claim that they cannot afford to remediate the problems they have created.

To deter fly-by-night firms, and to institutionalize the principle that "the polluter shall pay," ecological economist Robert Costanza has proposed a "precautionary principle polluter pays" (4P) assurance bond.[8, pgs. 209-215.] Using the "4P" approach, before a new technology, process or chemical could be introduced, the worst-case harm would be estimated in dollar terms. Then the proponent of the new activity would be required to post a bond for the full amount before startup.

Such "assurance bonds" are common in the construction industry today, to assure that a job will be completed on schedule and they are intended to keep "fly by night" firms out of the construction business where they might cut corners and endanger public health.

A "4P" bond effectively shifts the burden of proof onto the proponent â?" the burden of producing information to show that the activity is less harmful than was initially assumed (or, if harm becomes evident, to pay restitution by forfeiting a portion of the bond). A "4P" bond would also give the proponent
powerful financial incentives to reduce the worst case damages by, for example, adopting intrinsically safer alternatives.

Criticism #11: We don't need this new way of doing things because we're doing better than our predecessors did. We're even doing better than we ourselves did last year. We have new technologies that won't pollute as much as the old technologies polluted.

Response #11: The question isn't whether you are doing better than your predecessors, or better than you did last year. The question is, are you doing the best you can to protect human health and the environment? The precautionary approach assumes you want to achieve your own goals, and the community's goals, by the least-harmful means available. Precaution provides a way to learn whether you are measuring up to that standard. --Peter Montague ==============

[1] David Kriebel and others, "The Precautionary Principle in Environmental Science," Environmental Health Perspectives Vol. 109, No. 9 (Sept. 2001), pgs. 871-876. Available at http://www.rachel.org/library/getfile.cfm?ID=170

[2] Nancy Myers, "The Precautionary Principle Puts Values First," Bulletin of Science, Technology and Society Vol. 22, No. 3 (June, 2002), pgs. 210-219. Available at http://www.rachel.org/library/getfile.cfm?ID=188

[3] Donald Ludwig, Ray Hilborn and Carl Walters, "Uncertainty, Resource Exploitation, and Conservation: Lessons from History," Science Vol. 260 (April 2, 1993), pgs. 17, 36. Available at http://www.rachel.org/library/getfile.cfm?ID=201

[4] Peter Manus, "To a Candidate in Search of an Environmental Theme: Promote the Public trust," Stanford Environmental Law Journal Vol. 19 (May 2000), pg. 315 and following pages. Available at http://www.rachel.org/library/getfile.cfm?ID=234

[5] James T. Paul, "The Public Trust Doctrine: Who Has the Burden of Proof?" Paper presented July, 1996 in Honolulu, Hawaii, to a meeting of the Western Association of Wildlife and Fisheries Administrators. Available at http://www.rachel.org/library/getfile.cfm?ID=190

[6] See Rachel's #420 at http://www.rachel.org/bulletin/index.cfm?issue_ID=705

[7] Ruckelshaus, W. Risk in a Free Society. Risk Analysis. 1984; 4(3):157-162. Available at http://www.rachel.org/library/getfile.cfm?ID=361

[8] Robert Costanza and others, An Introduction to Ecological Economics (Boca Raton, Fla.: St. Lucie Press, 1997). The "4P" bond was described in Rachel's Environment & Health News #510, available at http://www.rachel.org/bulletin/index.cfm?issue_ID=613 . See also http://www.rachel.org/library/getfile.cfm?ID=310


Last changed: March 14, 2006